Explain the second principle of thermodynamics without the notion of entropy

If math is off-limits, then maybe an analogy will help.

(This answer elaborates on the first part of Nicolas's answer.)

Imagine a very large flat tray containing a very large number of coins all lying "face up". Suppose the tray is so large that the coins are all lying flat on the tray, without overlapping and with plenty of room between coins. Now suppose an earthquake hits. The tray shakes violently up and down, repeatedly flipping the coins in ways that do not inherently prefer any particular arrangement of the coins. After the earthquake is over, what percentage of the coins will be face up? The answer is "almost certainly less than 100 percent, and probably very close to 50 percent if the earthquake lasts long enough."

The reason for this outcome is identical to the reason for the second law of thermodynamics. For macroscopic purposes, we are normally only concerned with a few overall properties of the system. If it's a system of coins, then maybe we're only concerned with the number of face-up coins and don't care which coins are face-up. Or, if it's a system of molecules in a gas, maybe we're only concerned with the total volume and total energy and don't care exactly how the molecules are distributed throughout that volume or exactly how the total energy is divided up among them.

If the number of coins is large, then the number of possible configurations in which half of the coins are face-up is much, much larger than the number of possible configurations in which all of the coins are face-up. That's because for each configuration in which all of them are face-up, we can get a huge number of corresponding half-face-up configurations by randomly choosing which half of the coins to turn over. Since the earthquate doesn't inherently prefer any particular type of arrangement of the coins, the total number of face-up coins will tend to approach 50 percent, simply because the vast majority of possible configurations are configurations in which close to 50 percent of the coins are face up.

The situation for a gas of molecules is similar. For a given total number of molecules, the number of different arrangements in which they're distributed throughout the available space is much, much larger than the number of different arrangmenets in which they're all crammed into just half of the available space. Therefore, even if they start out crammed into half of the available space, as time passes and they jostle around in a way that doesn't inherently prefer any particular type of arrangement, we can rest assured that the molecules will end up distributed throughout the whole available space. The reason is identical to the reason in the coin-flipping analogy.

"Entropy" is essentially a measure of how many microstates (detailed configurations of coins) are compatible with a given macrostate (percentage of face-up coins). The second law of thermodynamics is simply the statement that as time passes and things get jostled around in a way that doesn't prefer any particular arrangement, the system tends to approach the macrostate that corresponds to the largest number of different microstates. In principle, the second law isn't a statement about what is or isn't possible. It's a statement about what is overwhelmingly likely or overwhelmingly unlikely. When dealing with such huge numbers as the number of air molecules in a typical room, "overwhelmingly unlikely" might as well mean "impossible".

It's worth emphasizing that "disorder" is not really the right concept here. The second law doesn't say that "disorder" always increases, whatever that even means. For example, we know that snowflakes can form naturally in cold clouds, and a snowflake is a beautifully ordered structure. This is perfectly compatible with the second law, and in fact the second law is an important ingredient in understanding why snowflakes do form. The second law says that if things are constantly changing in a way that doesn't prefer any particular arrangement, then... (etc). If particular arrangements are preferred in one part of the system, then we need to take that into account. The second law still holds overall, though, if we take the whole system into account. Any process that might enforce preferred arrangements in one part of the system necessarily relies on interactions with the rest of the system (the atmosphere, cosmic background radiation, and so on). If the rest of the system isn't acting in a way that prefers any particular arrangement of its microscopic constituents, then the second law still holds for the whole system.


There are several equivalent formulations of the second law. One states it takes work to move heat from a cooler body to a warmer one. This version allows us to discuss temperature instead of entropy. See here for details of how physical work allows air conditioning and refrigeration.


It depends on how precise and correct you need to be. The gist of the 2nd principle is that, since all microscopic configurations ("microstates") of a system are equiprobable, a system spontaneously evolves towards the observable state that corresponds to most configurations.

Of course, that's still a bit talking about entropy, since the entropy corresponds to the number of possible microstates. I wouldn't talk about "disorder" at all, since that description of entropy is often quite misleading.

Or you can use the many many formulations around heat flow, possible and impossible closed-cycle engines etc. ; but that's a bit more technical and doesn't give easily understanding of the reasons behind it.