How much of the Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem is constructively recoverable if the injections have retractions and decidable images?
CSB fails intuitionistically even under the conditions which you describe. This was proved by Van Dalen in A note on spread-cardinals, Compositio Mathematica, tome 20 (1968), p. 21-28.
Van Dalen gives an intuitionistic counterexample to CBS consisting of two compact subspaces of Baire space $\sigma, \tau$ and two injective functions $f, g$ between them.
These are such that $f(\sigma)$ is decidable in $\tau$ (and therefore a retract of $\tau$ since this is Baire topology) and vice versa $g(\tau)$ is decidable in $\sigma$ (and therefore a retract of $\sigma$), and yet there can be no bijection between $\sigma$ and $\tau$ in intuitionistic mathematics.
This shows that CSB cannot be proved constructively even under the conditions you mention.
[update 29 november to reflect the comments below:]
A fundamental reason why CSB fails in constructive mathematics is because in constructive mathematics total functions are 'always' continuous. Both in intuitionistic mathematics (INT) and in recursive mathematics (RUSS) total functions are provably continuous. Therefore a total function defined in BISH, being provably continuous in INT and RUSS, is 'always' continuous in BISH.
For constructive CSB this entails that we are dealing with a strong topological version: given two topological spaces $X,Y$ where $X$ can be embedded in $Y$ and vice versa, is it true that $X$ and $Y$ are homeomorphic?
One easily sees that this is only very rarely true. The extra conditions in your question somewhat amount to adding the following: 'where in addition the embedding of $X$ is clopen in $Y$ and vice versa'. This is topologically not enough to constructively ensure homeomorphism, as Van Dalen's example shows.
In general, because of this strong topological component, I have no hope at all that there are interesting (general enough) constructive versions of CSB. There can be truly topological theorems on what embeddability properties entail that two spaces are homeomorphic, but like I said, these theorems do not have the flavour of CSB in my eyes.
That the Cantor-Schröder-Bernstein theorem implies excluded middle was shown recently by Pierre Pradic and Chad Brown. If we check their proof (Corollary 12) we see that they almost use injections that satisfy your conditions. Namely, given a truth value $p \in \Omega$, they consider \begin{align*} f &: \mathbb{N}_\infty \to \{0 | p\} + \mathbb{N}_\infty \\ f &: x \mapsto \mathsf{inl}(x) \end{align*} and \begin{align*} g &: \{0 | p\} + \mathbb{N}_\infty \to\mathbb{N}_\infty \\ g &: \mathsf{inl}(0) \mapsto 0 \\ h &: \mathsf{inr}(x) \mapsto x + 1 \end{align*} The map $f$ has decidable image, namely the right summand, as well as a retraction, but the map $g$ has decidable image if and only if $0$ is in its image, which is equivalent to $p$.
As Frank points out, your statement cannot be proved, but it would also be interesting to see whether we can strengthen the proof by Pradic and Brown (doubtful), or adapt it so that under your conditions it proves a weak form of excluded middle. For example, suppose $p$ is semi-decidable, i.e., equivalent to $\exists k \in \mathbb{N} . c(k) = 1$, for some $c : \mathbb{N} \to \{0,1\}$. Can we then show that it is decidable using a CBS instance that satisfies your conditions?
Sorry that I come back to this question after 6 months, but I was looking for something else and duckduck brought me here. But if we go back even further, a short proof that a topos with NNO satisfies the Cantor-Schroeder-Bernstein if and only if it is boolean bubbled up on the CATEGORIES list in early 1994 (the following is from February '94):
The other way around, the validity of CSB in a topos ALMOST implies
that the topos is boolean. "Almost" means a slightly stronger version
needs to be considered:
(CSB*) if f:A->B and g:B->A are monics
then there is an iso h:A->B
such that for every x in A holds
h(x) = f(x) or h(x) = g^{-1}(x)
The usual set-theoretical proof of CSB (which goes through in boolean
toposes) actually yields (CSB*). In return, (CSB*) implies
booleanness. We assume that every topos has an object of natural
numbers.
PROPOSITION. A topos is boolean if and only if it satisfies (CSB*).
PROOF of the "if" part: Let X be a subobject of Y. We use (CSB*) to
construct its complement. Define
A = YxN
B = X+(YxN)
(where N is the object of natural numbers). Let f:A-->B be the
inclusion, and g:B-->A the unique arrow which maps X into the first
copy of Y in A, while it takes the copies of Y contained in B into the
second one, the third one and so on. (Formally, g is defined using the
universal property of coproducts, and the structure of N.) It is clear
that both f and g are monics.
By (CSB*), there is a bijection h:A-->B with h(x)=f(x) or
h(x)=g^{-1}(x). This means that the union of
C = {z | h(z)=f(z)} and
D = {z | h(z)=g^{-1}(z)}
covers A. On the other hand, the definitions of f and g imply that C
and D are disjoint. So they are complements in A. By pulling back C and D
along the inclusion of Y iso Yx{0} in A, we get two complementary
subobjects of Y. The claim is now that the intersection (pullback) X'
of D and Yx{0} is isomorphic to X -- so that the intersection of C and
Yx{0} yields the complement of X in Y.
First of all, each element <y,n> of D must surely be in the image of
g. Thus, if <y,0> is in D, then y must be in X. So X' is contained in
Xx{0}. The other way around, since h(C) is contained in f(C), the
intersection in B of X and h(C) must be empty. Therefore, X must be
contained in h(D): indeed, h is an iso, and the direct images h(C) and
h(D) must be complementary in B. But h(D) is contained in
g^{-1}(D). So X is in g^{-1}(D), i.e. g(X) is in D. Hence, Xx{0}=g(X)
is contained in X'.