Why is the classifying space of the natural numbers homotopy equivalent to the circle?

Method I: Symmetric products.

Contained inside the simplicial set $N\mathbb{N}$ is a copy of the simplicial circle $S^1$, generated by the zero-simplex and the 1-simplex $[1]$. This consists of all simplices of the form $e_i = (0,\ldots,0,1,0,\ldots,0)$, together with the basepoint $(0,\cdots,0)$, in the simplicial object.

Moreover, $N\mathbb{N}$ is, levelwise, a commutative monoid, and the face and degeneracy maps are maps of commutative monoids. In fact, $N\mathbb{N}$ visibly is, in level $p$, the free commutative monoid on $e_1, \ldots, e_p$, or the infinite symmetric product of the based set $(S^1)_p \subset (N\mathbb{N})_p$. As a simplicial set, then, $N\mathbb{N}$ is the infinite symmetric product of the based simplicial set $S^1$.

Geometric realization preserves finite products and quotients by group actions (hence symmetric products), as well as colimits, so the geometric realization is homeomorphic to the map $S^1 \to Sym^\infty S^1$ of topological spaces. On homotopy groups, by the Dold-Thom theorem, this is the map $\pi_* S^1 \to H_* S^1$, which is known to be an isomorphism.

Method II: Covering spaces.

Consider the auxiliary simplicial set $E$, which is the nerve of the poset $\mathbb{Z}$ under $\leq$. $E$ is contractible, for example because the functions $f(x) \equiv 0$ and $g(x) = max(x,0)$ satisfy $f(x) \leq g(x) \geq id(x)$; these inequalities give rise to natural transformations of categories and thus a two-stage homotopy from the identity to a trivial map.

The group $\mathbb{Z}$ acts on $E$ freely (and properly discontinuously on geometric realization) by translation. I claim that the quotient is isomorphic to $N\mathbb{N}$. The p-simplices of $E$ are all of the form $$ z \leq (z + n_1) \leq \cdots \leq (z + n_1 + \cdots + n_p) $$ and so the quotient can be identified with the collection of tuples $(n_1,\ldots,n_p)$. Composition adds adjacent $n_i$ and inserting an identity inserts $0$, so this really is the simplicial set $N\mathbb{N}$.

Since geometric realization preserves quotients by group actions, this makes $B\mathbb{N}$ into a $K(\mathbb{Z},1)$, and hence homotopy equivalent to $S^1$.


Indirect method:

Monoids are categories with one object. A simple calculation shows that the inclusion of categories N into Z has contractible homotopy fiber (which is the nerve of the category whose objects are the arrows of the one object category Z and whose arrows are commutative triangles of Z mediated by the elements of N). Thus Quillen's theorem A yields a homotopy equivalence of the corresponding nerves arising from the inclusion of underlying categories.

Direct method:

Consult this paper by Ken Brown: "The Geometry of Rewriting Systems"

You need only the simplest version of his method. With it one can show that the nerve of N and the nerve of Z have cellular models which differ only by collapses of simplices and thus have the same (simple) homotopy type.


Applying the functor "free $\mathbb Z$-module", the abelian monoid becomes a commutative ring $\mathbb Z[T]$, a polynomial ring in one variable. The bar construction, a simplicial set, becomes a simplicial abelian group: the bar construction for the augmented $\mathbb Z$-algebra. It follows that the homology of the classifying space is $Tor^{\mathbb Z[T]}(\mathbb Z,\mathbb Z)$, which is the homology of the circle. That, plus the fact the fundamental group is what it should be, plus the fact that the classifying space inherits its own commutative monoid structure, gives the result.