Are free monads also zippily applicative?

From the definition of Applicative:

If f is also a Monad, it should satisfy

  • pure = return

  • (<*>) = ap

  • (*>) = (>>)

So this implementation would break the applicative laws that say it must agree with the Monad instance.

That said, there's no reason you couldn't have a newtype wrapper for FreeMonad that didn't have a monad instance, but did have the above applicative instance

newtype Zip f a = Zip { runZip :: FreeMonad f a }
  deriving Functor

instance Applicative f => Applicative (Zip f) where -- ...

Yes, it looks like this is a lawful Applicative. Weird!

As @JosephSible points out, you can read off the identity, homomorphism and interchange laws immediately from the definitions. The only tricky one is the composition law.

pure (.) <*> u <*> v <*> w = u <*> (v <*> w)

There are eight cases to check, so strap in.

  • One case with three Returns: pure (.) <*> Return f <*> Return g <*> Return z
    • Follows trivially from associativity of (.).
  • Three cases with one Free:
    • pure (.) <*> Free u <*> Return g <*> Return z
      • Working backwards from Free u <*> (Return g <*> Return z) you get fmap (\f -> f (g z)) (Free u), so this follows from the functor law.
    • pure (.) <*> Return f <*> Free v <*> Return z
      fmap ($z) $ fmap f (Free v)
      fmap (\g -> f (g z)) (Free v)                  -- functor law
      fmap (f . ($z)) (Free v)
      fmap f (fmap ($z) (Free v))                    -- functor law
      Return f <$> (Free v <*> Return z)             -- RHS of `<*>` (first and second cases)
      QED
      
    • pure (.) <*> Return f <*> Return g <*> Free w
      • Reduces immediately to fmap (f . g) (Free w), so follows from the functor law.
  • Three cases with one Return:
    • pure (.) <*> Return f <*> Free v <*> Free w
      Free $ fmap (<*>) (fmap (fmap (f.)) v) <*> w
      Free $ fmap (\y z -> fmap (f.) y <*> z) v <*> w                  -- functor law
      Free $ fmap (\y z -> fmap (.) <*> Return f <*> y <*> z) v <*> w  -- definition of fmap, twice
      Free $ fmap (\y z -> Return f <*> (y <*> z)) v <*> w             -- composition
      Free $ fmap (\y z -> fmap f (y <*> z)) v <*> w                   -- RHS of fmap, definition of liftA2
      Free $ fmap (fmap f) $ fmap (<*>) v <*> w                        -- functor law, eta reduce
      fmap f $ Free $ liftA2 (<*>) v w                                 -- RHS of fmap
      Return f <*> Free v <*> Free w                                   -- RHS of <*>
      QED.
      
    • pure (.) <*> Free u <*> Return g <*> Free w
      Free ((fmap (fmap ($g))) (fmap (fmap (.)) u)) <*> Free w
      Free (fmap (fmap (\f -> f . g) u)) <*> Free w                    -- functor law, twice
      Free $ fmap (<*>) (fmap (fmap (\f -> f . g)) u) <*> w
      Free $ fmap (\x z -> fmap (\f -> f . g) x <*> z) u <*> w         -- functor law
      Free $ fmap (\x z -> pure (.) <*> x <*> Return g <*> z) u <*> w
      Free $ fmap (\x z -> x <*> (Return g <*> z)) u <*> w             -- composition
      Free $ fmap (<*>) u <*> fmap (Return g <*>) w                    -- https://gist.github.com/benjamin-hodgson/5b36259986055d32adea56d0a7fa688f
      Free u <*> fmap g w                                              -- RHS of <*> and fmap
      Free u <*> (Return g <*> w)
      QED.
      
    • pure (.) <*> Free u <*> Free v <*> Return z
      Free (fmap (<*>) (fmap (fmap (.)) u) <*> v) <*> Return z
      Free (fmap (\x y -> fmap (.) x <*> y) u <*> v) <*> Return z        -- functor law
      Free $ fmap (fmap ($z)) (fmap (\x y -> fmap (.) x <*> y) u <*> v)
      Free $ liftA2 (\x y -> (fmap ($z)) (fmap (.) x <*> y)) u v         -- see Lemma, with f = fmap ($z) and g x y = fmap (.) x <*> y
      Free $ liftA2 (\x y -> fmap (.) x <*> y <*> Return z) u v          -- interchange
      Free $ liftA2 (\x y -> x <*> (y <*> Return z)) u v                 -- composition
      Free $ liftA2 (\f g -> f <*> fmap ($z) g) u v                      -- interchange
      Free $ fmap (<*>) u <*> (fmap (fmap ($z)) v)                       -- https://gist.github.com/benjamin-hodgson/5b36259986055d32adea56d0a7fa688f
      Free u <*> Free (fmap (fmap ($z)) v)
      Free u <*> (Free v <*> Return z)
      QED.
      
  • Three Frees: pure (.) <*> Free u <*> Free v <*> Free w
    • This case only exercises the Free/Free case of <*>, whose right-hand side is identical to that of Compose's <*>. So this one follows from the correctness of Compose's instance.

For the pure (.) <*> Free u <*> Free v <*> Return z case I used a lemma:

Lemma: fmap f (fmap g u <*> v) = liftA2 (\x y -> f (g x y)) u v.

fmap f (fmap g u <*> v)
pure (.) <*> pure f <*> fmap g u <*> v  -- composition
fmap (f .) (fmap g u) <*> v             -- homomorphism
fmap ((f .) . g) u <*> v                -- functor law
liftA2 (\x y -> f (g x y)) u v          -- eta expand
QED.

Variously I'm using functor and applicative laws under the induction hypothesis.

This was pretty fun to prove! I'd love to see a formal proof in Coq or Agda (though I suspect the termination/positivity checker might mess it up).


For the sake of completeness, I will use this answer to expand on my comment above:

Though I didn't actually write down the proof, I believe the mixed-Free-and-Return cases of the composition law must hold due to parametricity. I also suspect that should be easier to show using the monoidal presentation.

The monoidal presentation of the Applicative instance here is:

unit = Return ()

Return x *&* v = (x,) <$> v
u *&* Return y = (,y) <$> u
-- I will also piggyback on the `Compose` applicative, as suggested above.
Free u *&* Free v = Free (getCompose (Compose u *&* Compose v))

Under the monoidal presentation, the composition/associativity law is:

(u *&* v) *&* w ~ u *&* (v *&* w)

Now let's consider one of its mixed cases; say, the Free-Return-Free one:

(Free fu *&* Return y) *&* Free fw ~ Free fu *&* (Return y *&* Free fw)

(Free fu *&* Return y) *&* Free fw -- LHS
((,y) <$> Free fu) *&* Free fw

Free fu *&* (Return y *&* Free fw) -- RHS
Free fu *&* ((y,) <$> Free fw)

Let's have a closer look at this left-hand side. (,y) <$> Free fu applies (,y) :: a -> (a, b) to the a values found in Free fu :: FreeMonad f a. Parametricity (or, more specifically, the free theorem for (*&*)) means that it doesn't matter if we do that before or after using (*&*). That means the left-hand side amounts to:

first (,y) <$> (Free fu *&* Free fw)

Analogously, the right-hand side becomes:

second (y,) <$> (Free fu *&* Free fw)

Since first (,y) :: (a, c) -> ((a, b), c) and second (y,) :: (a, c) -> (a, (b, c)) are the same up to reassociation of pairs, we have:

first (,y) <$> (Free fu *&* Free fw) ~ second (y,) <$> (Free fu *&* Free fw)
-- LHS ~ RHS

The other mixed cases can be dealt with analogously. For the rest of the proof, see Benjamin Hodgson's answer.