Proof that pi is transcendental that doesn't use the infinitude of primes

The infinitude of primes (more precisely, the existence of arbitrarily large primes) might actually be necessary to prove the transcendence of $\pi$. As I explained in an earlier answer, there are structures which satisfy many axioms of arithmetic but fail to prove the unboundedness of primes or the existence of irrational numbers. Shepherdson presented a simple method for constructing such models, I will present such a model where $\pi$ is rational!

The Shepherdson integers $S$ consist of all Puiseux polynomials of the form $$a = a_0 + a_1T^{q_1} + \cdots + a_kT^{q_k}$$ where $0 < q_1 < \cdots < q_k$ are rationals, $a_0 \in \mathbb{Z}$, and $a_1,\dots,a_k \in \mathbb{R}$. This is a discrete ordered domain, where $a < b$ iff the most significant term of $b-a$ is positive; this corresponds to making $T$ infinitely large. This ring $S$ satisfies open induction axioms $$\phi(0) \land \forall x(\phi(x) \to \phi(x+1)) \to \forall x(x \geq 0 \to \phi(x))$$ where $\phi(x)$ is a quantifier free formula (possibly with parameters). So the ring $S$ satisfies the same basic axioms as $\mathbb{Z}$, but only a very limited amount of induction. In the field of fractions of $S$, $\pi$ is equal to the ratio $\pi T/T$. In other words, $\pi$ is a rational number!

Is $\pi T/T$ really $\pi$? The integers form a subring of $S$, and if $p,q \in \mathbb{Z}$ then $p/q < \pi T/T$ in $S$ if and only if $p/q < \pi$ in $\mathbb{R}$. So $\pi T/T$ defines the same Dedekind cut as $\pi$ does, which is a very accurate description of $\pi$. Indeed, any proof of the transcendence of $\pi$ must ultimately be based on the comparison of $\pi$ and its powers with certain rational numbers, which $\pi T/T$ will accomplish just as well as the real number $\pi$. However, the usual definitions of $\pi$ are not easily formalizable in this basic theory, so there is much room for debate here and I wouldn't claim that $\pi T/T$ satisfies all reasonable definitions of $\pi$. Shepherdson only presented this argument for real algebraic numbers like $\sqrt{2}$, which have a finitary description in this theory and leave little room for debate. In any case, the conclusion to draw from this is that basic arithmetic with open induction does not suffice to prove that $\pi$, or any other real number, is irrational (never mind transcendental).

What about primes? In the ring $S$, the only primes are the ones from $\mathbb{Z}$. Although there are infinitely many primes in $S$, it is not true that there are arbitrarily large primes. For example, there are no primes larger than $T$. Thus $S$ is a model where the unboundedness of primes fails and so does the irrationality of $\pi$. This only shows that basic arithmetic with open induction does not suffice to prove either result. A possible line of attack to show that the unboundedness of primes is necessary to prove the transcendence of $\pi$ would be to show that the minimum amount of induction necessary to prove that $\pi$ is transcendental also suffices to prove the unboundedness of primes. Unfortunately, I do not know how much induction is necessary to prove the transcendence of $\pi$. (And the minimum amount of induction necessary to prove the unboundedness of primes is still an open problem.)


Well, here is a partial answer, which is a bit of a bummer. There is another Shepherdson domain $S_0$ similar to the above where $\pi$ is transcendental over $S_0$ and $S_0$ does not have arbitrarily large primes. This shows that the transcendence of $\pi$ does not imply the unboundedness of primes over basic arithmetic with open induction. The ring $S_0$ is the subring of $S$ where the coefficients of the Puiseux polynomial are restricted to be algebraic numbers. The unboundedness of primes fails in $S_0$ because the real algebraic numbers form a real closed field just like $\mathbb{R}$. The number $\pi$ is transcendental over $S_0$ because it is transcendental over the field of real algebraic numbers.

This is not entirely surprising since open induction is a very weak base theory and the Shepherdson type rings are very pathological. To constrain such pathologies Van Den Dries suggested requiring that the domain is integrally closed in its field of fractions; he called such domains normal but I don't know if this is standard terminology. Neither $S$ nor $S_0$ are normal. More convincing examples would be normal discrete ordered domains. The methods of Macintyre and Marker (Primes and their residue rings in models of open induction, MR1001418) suggest that normal analogues of $S$ and $S_0$ might exist.

The conclusion that I draw from this is that open induction is probably too weak a base theory to study this question. Stronger base theories run into the difficulty that it is still not known just how little induction is necessary to prove the unboundedness of primes. The next reasonable candidate is bounded-quantifier induction (IΔ0), which is not known to imply the unboundedness of primes. Using the Euler product $\pi^2/6 = \prod_p (1-p^{-2})^{-1}$ looks promising, but so far I can only make sense of this product in IΔ0 + Exp which is known to prove the unboundedness of primes.


Barry, this post is coming a "little bit" after your class ended, but I want to direct you to a paper on the Lindemann-Weierstrass theorem by Beukers, Bezivin, and Robba in the Amer. Math. Monthly in 1990: https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/2324683.pdf. They give a proof of LW theorem that does not explicitly involve a choice of an auxiliary prime number, and it would be a good exercise to work out what the proof is saying in the special case of the number $\pi$ to see more directly how it proves $\pi$ is transcendental, or more generally how it shows $e^\alpha$ is transcendental when $\alpha$ is a nonzero algebraic number (the Lindemann part of LW) without dealing with the more general setting of a finite set of algebraic $\alpha_i$ (the Weierstrass part of LW). As indicated at the start of the paper by Beukers et al., the proof was inspired by ideas from $p$-adic analysis, but their paper is a simplified version that does not have any explicit dependence on $p$-adic notions.

I don't agree with the post claiming infinitude of primes "might be necessary" to prove transcendence of $\pi$. Just because you are working within an axiomatic framework that would allow you to prove infinitude of primes doesn't mean you ought to be required to do that for what you want, so that whole matter seems irrelevant to answering your question. If I am proving the Eisenstein irreducibility criterion in $\mathbf Z[x]$ you can't seriously tell me that I must go on a detour in the middle of the proof and prove $\mathbf Z[i]$ is a Euclidean domain just because it is logically possible with the axioms I am allowing. In any case, I think the paper I linked to should settle your question in an affirmative way that you were seeking.

UPDATE: The impression that you need infinitely many primes to prove transcendence results is incorrect, not because there are proofs that avoid it like the comparatively recent proof I mention above or older proofs I did not mention, but because even the proofs that mention it don't really need it. For example, look at the two proofs of transcendence of $e$ and $\pi$ here (pp. 3-5) and here. (In case those links change in the future, the proofs are essentially the same as those on pp. 4-6 of Baker's book "Transcendental Number Theory".) The way the proofs work is that an expression $J_p$ is introduced that depends on a prime $p$ (and some fixed data like a hypothetical algebraic relation for the number to be proved transcendental) and $J_p$ is shown to satisfy two properties: (i) a growth estimate $|J_p| \leq c^p$, where $c$ is independent of $p$ and (ii) $J_p$ is a sum of two integers, one being a multiple of $p!$ and the other being a multiple of $(p-1)!$ that for all large prime $p$ is not a multiple of $p!$, so $J_p$ is an integer multiple of $(p-1)$! that is not zero. Therefore $|J_p| \geq (p-1)!$, which contradicts the growth estimate in (i) since we can't have $(m-1)! \leq c^m$ for large $m$. How is the primality of $p$ really used? Its only purpose is to be an arbitrarily large number that is relatively prime to a couple of specific nonzero integers. But there is no need to rely on prime numbers to achieve that: if you want a huge integer $m$ relatively prime to two nonzero integers $a$ and $b$, just take $m = |ab|M + 1$ for a huge integer $M$. So you can work with numbers in such an arithmetic progression in place of a large prime number $p$ in the proof. (Personally I'd also pass to the integer $J_m/(m-1)!$ so the bounds $0 < |J_m/(m-1)!| \leq c^m/(m-1)!$ lead to the "no integers between $0$ and $1$" contradiction once $c^m/(m-1)!< 1$, but that's a matter of taste.)

Of course the idea of creating numbers relatively prime to particular numbers by taking a multiple of their product and adding $1$ is the main idea in Euclid's proof of the infinitude of the primes, so we aren't bypassing a method that can lead to infinitely many primes but we are bypassing any need for prime numbers in the proof that uses them.

The idea of using a large prime in proofs of the transcendence of $e$ and $\pi$ is due to Hurwitz, who added this detail to a proof by Hilbert that relies on divisibility properties but not on primes. Mahler discusses this in his Springer Lecture Notes in Math "Lectures on Transcendental Numbers" (1976). The volume is available online here, and while most chapters are behind a paywall the last part called Back Matter is not, and that's the part relevant to us. Mahler presents Hilbert's proof starting on p. 237. On p. 243 he mentions Hurwitz's idea of using a prime instead of a number in a simply constructed arithmetic progression and explains why he thinks this "seemingly simpler" approach of Hurwitz is actually not a good idea.


I recommend the book Irrational Numbers by Ivan Niven, one of the M.A.A. Carus Monographs and available as a paperback. He proves irrationality of $\pi$ and $\pi^2$ much earlier, then shows that $\pi$ is also transcendental with the Lindemann theorem, chapter 9. I really like this book.

As you know from teaching your class, impossibility of the compass and straightedge constructions does not need anywhere near the full weight of transcendence, merely that the associated constant not lie in a tower of fields that expresses the idea of taking square roots, see

On using field extensions to prove the impossiblity of a straightedge and compass construction

or Appendix C in Galois Theory by Joseph Rotman, where he uses "only elementary field theory; no Galois theory is required." However, in line with your complaint, I should admit that I do not personally know of any proof that shows $\pi$ is not among the "constructible numbers" except for proofs of transcendence.