Relative sizes of sets of integers and rationals revisited - how do I make sense of this?

Of course, there are other notions of size. In particular, your notion of "a partial order based on inclusion of sets" is a very fruitful concept which has been used frequently. As a quick example, there is a technique in mathematical logic/set theory called "forcing" which is used to show that certain mathematical statements are unprovable. Forcing often starts with a partial ordered set where the order is given by inclusion of subsets.

In terms of the everyday world interpretation of the word "size", there are (at least) two problems with the using the partial order given by inclusion of subsets. The first is, as you said, a partial order: there are two sets which cannot be compared, i.e., there are 2 sets where you cannot say one is bigger than the other. The second is that two things will have the same size precisely when the two things are absolutely the same. There is no notion of different things which happen to be the same size - that can't happen in this partial order.

For example, lets say we're looking at subsets of the integers. You pull out your favorite subset: all the odd integers and I pull out mine: all the even integers. Using the partial order definition of size, these two sets are incomparable. Mine is neither bigger than, smaller than, or the same size as yours. To contrast that, using the cardinality notion of size, they have the same size. This is evidenced by simply taking everything in your set and adding 1 to it to get everything in my set. For an even more absurd example, consider the set {0} and the set {1}. One would expect these two sets to have the same notion of "size" (for any notion of "size"!), but using the partial order notion, one cannot compare these two sets.

By contrast, cardinality (or, the way I used "size" in the previous link) is defined on ALL sets (assuming the axiom of choice), even those which a priori have no subset relation. And there are many examples of sets which have the same cardinality, but which are not equal. (For example, the set of evens and odds, or the sets {0} and {1}).


Is there, for example, some alternative named "size" definition consistent with the partial ordering given by the is-a-proper-subset-of operator?

There is such an alternative. Maybe two, depending on how you count. Some references:

  • Sets and Their Sizes (my dissertation, 1981) at http://arxiv.org/abs/math/0106100. Offers a general theory of set size that includes a proper-subset principle, trichotomy, and, in fact, all statements true of sizes of finite sets (in a restricted language) and constructs a model over sets of natural numbers that respects the ordering by asymptotic density.
  • An article, Measuring the size of infinite collections of natural numbers: Was Cantor's theory of infinite number inevitable? by Paolo Mancosu that provides a good historical perspective and mentions more recent - and much more extensive - work on developing such a theory by V. Benci, M. Di Nasso, and M. Forti. Available at: http://philpapers.org/rec/MANMTS.
  • A critical view of such theories, Set Size and the Part Whole Principle, by Matthew Parker, at philpapers.org as PARSSA-3. (It seems I've run out of link power!)

Fred M. Katz


Purely set theoretically, cardinality is the right way to think of the "size" of a set. A bijection $f:A\to B$ simply renames each element $x$ in $A$ to $f(x)$, and one reasonably wants the size of a set not to depend on the names given to its elements.

There are other notions of size if you let your sets have more structure. The natural density (if it exists) of a subset $A$ of the natural numbers $\mathbb N$ can be thought as the relative size of $A$ to $\mathbb N$. The natural density of the even numbers is $1/2$, for example, so one might say there are half as many even natural numbers as there are natural numbers altogether. If $A$ and $B$ have natural densities $d(A)$ and $d(B)$, and $A\subseteq B\subseteq \mathbb N$, then $d(A)\leq d(B)$. Not all subsets of $\mathbb N$ have a natural density though, so in particular we can't compare the "sizes" of all sets of naturals.

Another possibility is considering the (measurable) subsets of a set $X$ equipped with a measure $m$. If $A$ and $B$ are measurable subsets of $X$, and $A\subseteq B$, then $m(A)\leq m(B)$. For example, we can use the Lebesgue measure $m$ on $X=\mathbb R$, which gives measure 1 to the interval $[0,1]$ and measure $1/2$ to the interval $[0,1/2]$. But again, not all subsets of $X$ are measurable, so not all sets can be compared size-wise this way.

Note that in both the approaches above, we can only compare the size of a set relative to some other fixed set ($\mathbb N$ or $X$). Any finite set and the set of rational numbers both have measure 0 with respect to the Lebesgue measure on $\mathbb R$, for example, so we would be forced to admit them to have the same size in this setting.